ТОП просматриваемых книг сайта:
Statistics and the Evaluation of Evidence for Forensic Scientists. Franco Taroni
Читать онлайн.Название Statistics and the Evaluation of Evidence for Forensic Scientists
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9781119245414
Автор произведения Franco Taroni
Жанр Математика
Издательство John Wiley & Sons Limited
Two books that take the form of textbooks on statistics for lawyers are Vito and Latessa (1989) and Finkelstein and Levin (2015). The former focusses on the presentation of statistical concepts commonly used in criminal justice research. It provides criminological examples to demonstrate the calculation of basic statistics. The latter introduces rather more advanced statistical techniques and again uses case studies to illustrate the techniques.
Historically, the particular area of discrimination litigation is covered by a set of papers edited by Kaye and Aickin (1986). This starts by outlining the legal doctrines that underlie discrimination litigation. In particular, there is a fundamental issue relating to discrimination in hiring. The definition of the relevant market from which an employer hires has to be made very clear. For example, consider the case of a man who applies, but is rejected, for a secretarial position. Is the relevant population the general population, the representation of men amongst secretaries in the local labour force, or the percentage of male applicants? The choice of a suitable reference population is also one with which the forensic scientist has to be concerned. This is discussed at several points in this book, see, for example, Sections 5.5.3.4 and 6.1.
Another textbook, which comes in two volumes, is Gastwirth (1998a,b). The book is concerned with civil cases and ‘is designed to introduce statistical concepts and their proper use to lawyers and interested policy makers
’ (volume 1, p. xvii). Two areas are stressed, which are usually given less emphasis in most statistical textbooks. The first area is concerned with measures of relative or comparative inequality. These are important because many legal cases are concerned with issues of fairness or equal treatment. The second area is concerned with the combination of results of several related statistical studies. This is important because existing administrative records or currently available studies often have to be used to make legal decisions and public policy; it is not possible to undertake further research. Gastwirth (2000) has also edited a collection of essays on statistical science in the courtroom, some of which are directly relevant for this current book and will be referred to as appropriate.A collection of papers on Statistics and Public Policy has been edited by Fairley and Mosteller (1977). One issue in the book, which relates to a particularly infamous case, the Collins case, is discussed in detail later (Section 3.4). Other articles concern policy issues and decision making.
Of further interest is a book (Kadane 2008) explicitly entitled ‘Statistics and the Law’, which considers the question ‘how can lawyers and statisticians best collaborate in a court of law to present statistics in the most clear and persuasive manner?’. With the use of case studies that refer to employment, jury behaviour, fraud, taxes, and aspects of patents, there is clarification of what a statistician and what a lawyer should know for a fruitful collaboration.
Other recent publications on the interaction between law and statistics are, for example, Dawid et al. (2014), Kadane (2018a,b), Kaye (2017a,b), and Gastwirth (2017).
The remit of this book is one that is not covered by these others in great detail. The use of statistics in forensic science in general is discussed in a collection of essays edited by Aitken and Stoney (1991). The remit of this book is to describe statistical procedures for the evaluation of evidence for forensic scientists. This will be done primarily through a Bayesian approach, the principle of which was described in Peirce (1878). It was developed further in the work of I.J. Good and A.M. Turing as code‐breakers at Bletchley Park during World War Two. A brief review of the history was given in Good (1991). A history of the Bayesian approach for a lay audience was given in Bertsch McGrayne (2011). An essay on the topic of probability and the weighing of evidence was written by Good (1950). This also referred to entropy (Shannon 1948), the expected amount of information from an experiment, and Good remarked that the expected weight of evidence in favour of a hypothesis
and against its complement is equal to the difference of the entropies assuming and , respectively. A brief discussion of a frequentist approach and the problems associated with it is given in Section 3.6 (see also Taroni et al. 2016). A general review of the Bayesian approach was given by Fienberg (2006).It is of interest to note that a high proportion of situations involving the so‐called objective presentation of statistical evidence uses the frequentist approach with tests of significance (Fienberg and Schervish 1986).2 However, Fienberg and Schervish go on to say that the majority of examples cited for the use of the Bayesian approach are in the area of identification evidence. It is this area that is the main focus of this book, and it is Bayesian analyses that will form the basis for the evaluation of evidence as discussed here. Examples of the applications of such analyses to legal matters include Cullison (1969), Finkelstein and Fairley (1970, 1971), Fairley (1973), Lempert (1977), Lindley (1975, 1977b,c), Fienberg and Kadane (1983), Lempert (1986), Redmayne (1995, 1997), Friedman (1996), Redmayne (2002), Anderson et al. (2005), Robertson et al. (2016), and Adam (2016).
Another approach that will not be discussed here is that of Shafer (1976, 1982). This concerns so‐called belief functions, see Section 3.1. The theory of belief functions is a very sophisticated theory for assessing uncertainty that endeavours to answer criticisms of both the frequentist and Bayesian approaches to inference. Belief functions are non‐additive in the sense that belief in an event
[denoted ] and belief in the opposite of [denoted ] do not sum to 1. See also Shafer (1978) for a historical discussion of non‐additivity. Further discussion is beyond the scope of this book. Practical applications are few. One such, however, is to the evaluation of evidence concerning the refractive index of glass (Shafer 1982). More recent developments of the role of belief functions in law for burdens of proof and in forensic science with a discussion of the island problem (Section 6.1.6.3) and parental identification are given in Nance (2019) and Kerkvliet and Meester (2016).It is very tempting when assessing evidence to try to determine a value for the probability of the so‐called probandum of interest (or the ultimate issue) such as the true guilt of a PoI (as distinct from a verdict of guilty, which may or may not be correct), or a value for the odds in favour of guilt and perhaps even to reach a decision regarding the PoI's guilt. However, this is the role of the jury and/or judge. It is not the role of the forensic scientist or statistical expert witness to give an opinion on this (Evett 1983). It is permissible for the scientist to say that the evidence is 1000 times more likely, say, if the PoI is the offender than if he is not the offender. It is not permissible to interpret this to say that, because