ТОП просматриваемых книг сайта:
The Power In The Land. Fred Harrison
Читать онлайн.Название The Power In The Land
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9780856835438
Автор произведения Fred Harrison
Жанр Социология
Издательство Bookwire
18 W. Rees-Mogg, ‘My resumption of liberty’, The Times, 7.3.81.
2 Laissez Faire: Adam Smith’s Version
Adam Smith believed that he was recommending the economics of the free market when he wrote The Wealth of Nations. He thought that his theoretical system had, as its dynamic principle, the competitive spirit; that, within the framework of natural justice, economic growth would be enjoyed by the three ‘original great orders’ which comprised civilized society — the land-lords, capitalists and labourers. He was wrong.
Smith was not wrong in thinking that theoretically the economics of capitalist competition could function efficiently to the advantage of all. His cr tor arose from the deduction that his specific system provided such an outcome, that it would secure the dual aim of freeing people to pursue private aims while guaranteeing the natural harmony of the total system. For his was not a description of how to construct a free market: he insulated the landlords from the competitive spirit. Until this is appreciated the science of political economy will be severely limited in its influence on public policy.
For two centuries Smith’s book has been the ‘bible’ for the buccaneering entrepreneurs who built factories and mass-produced cheap goods, and for the rational thinkers — the technologists, scientists and engineers and organisational managers — who trampled theological mysticism under foot in favour of science. But when Smith penned The Wealth of Nations he betrayed the spirit of the free market. At the abstract level, his testament promoted a philosophy that relentlessly exposed the special privileges and the monopoly power that politicians and manufacturers tried to invoke to their profitable advantage, but the book also set the seal of approval on an institutional framework that crippled capitalism at its conception. And so Adam Smith’s victims were not just the toiling masses who were subjected to the tortuous economic pressures that reduced so many of them to misery. A death blow was also administered to the very idea of the free market.
Lutissez faire is now discredited because, by popular agreement, it has failed to work to everyone’s satisfaction. It was out of resignation to this ‘failure’ that the philosophy of the New Deal developed: the belief that a mixed economy would do what the free market was incapable of accomplishing. But the interpretation of the history of industrial society ever since publication of The Wealth of Nations has geen grossly defective, which is why the critics have been able to conclude that unrestrained competition is inherently evil. Collective action, collective ownership of capital and centralised bureaucratic planning are now — in degrees varying only according to vested interests — acclaimed as the remedial alternatives.
The analyses have been wrong because the historians and social scientists have taken all the tenets of Adam Smith as necessarily intrinsic to the capitalist market. They have pursued their enquiries into a malfunctioning system without questioning the necessity for those property rights which have underpinned that system; without questioning whether, had a modified configuration of property rights existed, the free market might have achieved its goals without the evil consequences which have beset industrial society. Across the political spectrum, from Marxist left to conservative right, the arguments and counter-arguments have progressed without adequate reflection on whether a reform of the principles of property ownership and the rationale which motivates the owners of these rights might be sufficient to improve the operations of the free market without recourse to those bureaucratic modifications that deny the ‘perfect liberty’ that Smith wished to attain.
The debate about capitalism as a mode of production, therefore, has been in the terms validated by Adam Smith. But contrary to what he thought he was doing — and his readers interpreted him as doing1—Smith developed an economic framework which entailed a fatal element of monopoly power. He wrote about an ‘invisible hand’ guiding the system to the benefit of everyone, but he recommended the preservation of a structure of property rights which by its very nature struck at the heart of individual liberty and economic prosperity.
Critics, then, are opponents of Adam Smith — not of laissez faire. For the freely competitive market system with a capitalistic ethos has yet to be put to trial. Responsibility for the slums of Bolton in the 19th century, and the hunger of the Jarrow marchers in the 20th century, must be laid at the feet of Adam Smith and the politicians and practitioners who happily accepted his values; these tragedies, as we shall see, are not a necessary part of laissez faire capitalism. The search for a system which combines personal freedom and social stability with economic prosperity for everyone is a realisable dream, and its pursuit must start with an analysis of the defects in the philosophical justification advanced to legitimise the history of western industrial society: The Wealth of Nations.
Dr Smith was a careful Scottish scholar. He had taught at the University of Edinburgh, travelled to France where he studied the Physiocratic system of economics, and was an accomplished logician and natural scientist. His great book was not specifically prepared for the Industrial Revolution which was fermenting all around him. He wanted to define the principles of a free and just economic system of relevance to any civilized society. Indeed, surprisingly, he was not well acquainted with the great strides in mechanical inventions which characterised the two decades during which he wrote the book which he published in 1776.2
The clues to Smith’s fatal errors were contained in his first book, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759),3 which was a discourse on ethics. In this, he distorted the way in which income was divided between the landlords and the landless. In doing so, however, he linked ‘the invisible hand’ with the process, and the free market was generally held to be guilty of what subsequently happened.
Smith knew the facts. The natural fertility of the earth, nurtured by human labour, increased the output that fed a greater multitude. But, he insisted:
It is to no purpose that the proud and unfeeling landlord views his extensive fields, and without a thought for the wants of his brethren, in imagination consumes himself the whole harvest that grows upon them. The homely and vulgar proverb, that the eye is larger than the belly, never was more fully verified than with regard to him.4
Smith insisted that, given the limited capacities of the landlord’s belly, he was obliged to ‘distribute’ his surplus food. The rich ‘consume little more than the poor; and in spite of their natural selfishness and rapacity... they divide with the poor the produce of all their improvements’. Underpinning the whole structure of Adam Smith’s economics was this naive claim that landlords shared the surplus output among every person in society; more than that, however, the distribution was effectively an equal one. Of landlords, he said:
They are led by an invisible hand to make nearly the same distribution of the necessaries of life which would have been made had the earth been divided into equal portions among all its inhabitants; and thus, without intending it, without knowing it, advance the interest of the society, and afford means to the multiplication of the species.5
So land redistribution was not on the agenda of reforms that might be necessary to improve the new mode of production. For ‘the invisible hand’ ensured that people enjoyed ‘nearly the same distribution’ as if the earth had been divided into equal portions among all.
Smith insulated the landlords from criticism by claiming that they were not responsible for the existing distribution of property rights, and that in any event nobody was really excluded from a share of wealth: