Скачать книгу

required to do’ are answered in part by the underlying processes of counting. Political representation is determined by the counting of votes and of voters. The relative weighting of particular people and groups in the distributions of benefits, and of responsibilities, is determined by the counting of people for each purpose.

      Crucially, the gathering of this data is far from unbiased (what Foucault terms ‘governmentality’). Statistics and metrics do not simply appear fully formed, nor do they emerge from some neutral process of knowledge search, ready to be applied objectively to an optimal policy analysis. Instead, the interests of those who govern will be reflected in the very means of counting. Data is constructed in such a way as to support the emergence of social structures that are more ‘governable’.

      In Foucault’s conception, this process can be a positive one:1

      We must cease once and for all to describe the effects of power in negative terms: it ‘excludes’, it ‘represses’, it ‘censors’, it ‘abstracts’, it ‘masks’, it ‘conceals’. In fact, power produces; it produces reality; it produces domains of objects and rituals of truth. The individual and the knowledge that may be gained of him belong to this production.

      The key point for our purposes is that the production of statistics and metrics, the process of counting that underpins state functions, is not abstract but deliberately willed. Most bluntly, this applies to the planning approaches that James C. Scott memorably dissects in Seeing Like a State:2

      The experience of the UN Millennium Development Goals (MDGs), discussed later, provides a good illustration of the point that being blind to the characteristics of people, households and groups does not result in neutral progress – quite the opposite. Recognizing the ‘markings’ of ‘subjects’, or refusing to do so, is likely to change significantly the processes of both planning and policy enactment.

      Alain Desrosières identifies four attitudes of statisticians and others to the reality or otherwise of statistics.3 The most obvious, which he labels ‘metrological realism’, rests on the assumption of some permanent reality, which is independent of any observation apparatus – so that quantitative social sciences could ultimately attain equivalent status to natural sciences.

      In contrast, ‘accounting realism’ relates to a more limited space (internal to an enterprise or economic), but offers the illusory promise of rational, testable, provable numbers through double-entry bookkeeping. Illusory, because the numbers necessarily depend on a whole series of judgements – from those involved in the underlying business (or government of, say, a national economy), to the accountants involved directly in compiling the public record, and eventually to those behind the accounting frameworks in use.

      The validity of this ‘reality’ depends in turn upon trust in those accountants and others – not in some objectively verifiable and unique set of data. If you’re tempted to think accounting realism is anything but illusory, just ask anyone who has ever looked at the annual report of a multinational company to try to work out whether they paid the right tax, at the right time, in the right place.

      This point is extended in an important contribution by Wendy Espeland and Mitchell Stevens, which makes the case that ‘quantification is fundamentally social – an artefact of human action, imagination, ambition, accomplishment, and failing’.5 Measures not only reflect a view of people or things, but also lead people to change their behaviour – including policymakers, thereby creating the possibility of circular feedback between the (in any case overlapping) processes of government and measurement. That circularity is an inevitable feature, and can be both vicious and virtuous. In the case of the uncounted, poor data can promote poor policy, which in turn undermines the scope to improve data; but data improvements can also be self-reinforcing, driving a positive loop of better policy.

      The choice of who and what go uncounted, excluded either from the gathered statistics or from the chosen metrics, is equally a question of power. And the roles of power and social construction in counting are not optional. There is no ‘neutral’ option in which counting decisions are taken in a vacuum, free from political concerns. And there are no meaningful counting decisions that do not have political implications.

      We cannot design a system that inoculates societies from these core characteristics of counting. But we can inoculate ourselves to a degree, from the ‘seduction of quantification’, by opening our eyes to it: by understanding the central dynamics, and the possible nature and extent of the biases that result. We can count better. And if we do, the world can be better.

      In this book, I look at a range of important counting choices as they are actually made. I consider the implications for inequality, for governance and for human progress. I use the term ‘uncounted’ to describe a politically motivated failure to count. This takes two main forms, and each has direct implications for inequalities.

      First, there may be people and groups at the bottom of distributions (e.g., income) whose ‘uncounting’ adds another level to their marginalization – for example, where they are absent from statistics that underpin political representation (‘who decides’) and also inform policy prioritization (‘what people get’). Second, there may be people and groups at the top of distributions who are further empowered by being able to go uncounted – not least by hiding income and wealth from taxation and regulation (‘what people are required to do’). The uncounted at the bottom are excluded; the uncounted at the top are escaping.

Скачать книгу