Скачать книгу

Endowment Fund. Acc. n.: 914.2005.© 2017. Digital image, The Museum of Modern Art, New York/Scala, Florence

      Every effort has been made to trace all copyright holders, but if any have been overlooked the publisher will be pleased to include any necessary credits in any subsequent reprint or edition.

      For further information on Polity, visit our website: politybooks.com

      Marcel Proust, À l’ombre des jeunes filles en fleur, p. 199

      It is well known that Modernism in the visual arts finds an intellectual basis in Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Judgment (1790), and more recently in the work of the pivotal American critics Clement Greenberg and Michael Fried. Kant is often called a “formalist” in his approach to art, despite not using the term in this connection. But he does speak of formalism in his ethical theory, and we will see that the reasons that motivate the term’s appearance in one case apply to the other as well. Use of the word “formalist” to describe Greenberg and Fried encounters more resistance, at least in circles where these authors are viewed favorably, and special efforts are made to exempt Fried from this designation. Stephen Melville, for instance, laments “what is still far too often presented as Greenberg and Fried’s Kantian formalism,” while Richard Moran objects that formalism “seems an inapt term to characterize [Fried’s] brilliant readings of French painting …”1 The present book will nonetheless speak of Greenberg and Fried as Kantian formalists, though I am far more sympathetic to these authors than most who do so; indeed, I regard both authors as classics whose importance goes well beyond the sphere of art. Although I am well aware that Greenberg was cold to the word “formalism,” and that Fried remains even more so, the term fits them perfectly well in the sense to be developed in this book. My goal in saying so is not to impose unwanted terminology on anyone, but to renew focus on what is living and what is dead in Kant’s approach to art, and in his philosophical position more generally. No intellectual figure dominates the past two-and-a-half centuries like Kant, and previous attempts to get beyond him have never really gotten to the heart of the matter – the titanic efforts of German Idealism notwithstanding. Thus, we remain haunted by Kant’s strengths and limitations to this day.

Скачать книгу