Скачать книгу

to conceive of a suitable sequence. Do we repeat the same trial with a different jury; or with the same jury bur different lawyers; or do we take all Scottish trials; or only Scottish trials for the same offence? The whole idea of chance is preposterous in this context. (p. 48)

      The example makes clear that a definition of probability based on the long‐run relative frequency of an event is inapplicable in many situations arising in real life. There are implicit assumptions that must apply in each of the classical and frequentist definitions. These assumptions are, first, that according to our state of knowledge, all cases are equally likely, and, second, that it is theoretically possible to perform an experiment a large number of times under identical conditions. Use of these assumptions to assign a numerical value to a probability implies a judgement that these assumptions are satisfied. A definition of probability that seeks to avoid subjectivity is based on an acceptance of assumptions that are inherently subjective. The frequentist view presumes the possibility of the performance of a long sequence of experiments under identical conditions, with each experiment being physically independent of all other experiments. These assumptions are typically unachievable in many different applied contexts such as history, law, economics, medicine, and, especially, forensic science. In these contexts, the events of interest are usually not the result of repetitive or replicable processes. On the contrary, they are unique.

       There are many philosophically oriented fundamental ideas of probability. Perhaps the most practical basic approach to the subject lies in the concept of frequency, in which statements of probability express the relative frequencies of repeated events. [ images ] For practical use in criminalistics, it is of little interest what might happen in a long series of trials; the crime is committed only once. Of what use, then, is the above frequency concept? The answer to this lies in another way of looking at probability, which is to consider it as a degree of belief. (p. 514)

      Such complications do not arise with the subjective interpretation of probability because that interpretation does not consider probability as a feature of the external world. Instead probability is understood as a notion that describes the relationship between a person (e.g. You, the reader) who makes a statement of uncertainty and the real world to which that statement relates and in which the person acts. With the subjective concept of probability, it is therefore very reasonable to assign a probability to events that are not repeatable, for example, as in a given judicial context. An extended discussion on the limitations of the classical and frequentist definitions of probability can be found in Taroni et al. (2018).

      1.7.5 Subjective Definition of Probability

      Jurists are also interested in probabilistic reasoning using subjective probabilities, notably probabilities related to the credibility of witnesses and the conclusions that might be drawn from their testimony.

      Subjective probability may be found in many scientific areas (Press and Tanur 2001). In physics, for example, Schrödinger (1947) wrote

       Since the knowledge may be different with different persons or with the same person at different times, they may anticipate the same event with more or less confidence and thus different numerical probabilities may be attached to the same event. (p. 53)

      He then added that

       Thus, whenever we speak loosely of the probability of an event, it is always to be understood: probability with regard to a certain given state of knowledge. (p. 54)

      The same perspective is expressed by de Finetti in his famous sentence ‘Probability does not exist’ (in things) (de Finetti 1975, p. x). Probability is not something that can be known or not known, probabilities are states of mind, not states of nature. This aphorism can also be found in previous statistical and philosophical literature (i.e. de Morgan 1838; Jaynes 2003; Jevons 1913; Maxwell 1990). For example, Jevons (1913) wrote

       Probability belongs wholly to the mind. This is proved by the fact that different minds may regard the very same event at the same time with widely different degrees of probability [ images ,] Probability thus belongs to our mental condition, to the light in which we regard events, the occurrence or non‐occurrence of which is certain in themselves. (p. 198)

      In summary, a person's assessment of their degree of belief (subjective probability) in the truth of a given statement or in the occurrence of an event (i) depends on information, (ii) may change as the information changes, and (iii) may differ from the assessment of others because different individuals may have different information or assessment criteria. In Savage's words (Savage 1954)

       Probabilistic views hold that probability measures the confidence that a particular individual has in the truth of a particular proposition, for example, the probability that it will rain tomorrow. These views postulate that the individual concerned is in some way ‘reasonable’, but they do not deny the possibility that two reasonable individuals faced with the same information may have different degrees of confidence in the truth of the same proposition. (p. 3)

      The only constraint in the assessment – as noted in Section 1.7.2 – is that it must be coherent. Coherence may be understood through consideration of subjective probability in terms of betting, for example, on the outcome of a horse race. For the probabilities on winning

Скачать книгу