Скачать книгу

man does these with his soul’ (DA 408b12–15).4 This observation marks a crucial divide between the Aristotelian conception and the later Cartesian one, inasmuch as Descartes ascribed all psychological functions to the mind (see §1.2). It also marks a crucial divide between Aristotelian thought and contemporary conceptions, inasmuch as current cognitive neuroscientists (and others) ascribe a multitude of psychological (especially cognitive and volitional) functions to the brain (see §3.1). To do so is in effect to ascribe to a part of an animal attributes which it makes sense to ascribe only to the animal as a whole.

       Aristotle’ s conception of the sensus communis

      The sensus communis – a master organ for unifying sensibles in perception

      1 We do not see that we are seeing or hear that we are hearing. Nevertheless, Aristotle held, we do perceive that we are seeing or hearing – and that is one of the functions of the common sense.11 (Some contemporary neuroscientists and neuropsychologists who are engaged in the investigation of ‘blind-sight’ assign to some part of the brain the function of a self-monitoring device to fulfil the same function.12) However, the reasoning is faulty, since we do not perceive that we see or hear; rather, when we see or hear, we can say that we do so – but not because we in any sense perceive that we do. This form of self-awareness needs elucidation, but not by this route.

      2 By means of the sense of sight, we discriminate white from red, and by means of taste, we distinguish sweet from sour. But, Aristotle curiously observes, we also discriminate white from sweet and red from sour – and that neither by sight nor by taste.13 So, he infers, there must be some master faculty of perception which is employed to fulfil this function (DA 426b).

      3 Since sleep affects all the sense-faculties (i.e. we do not see, hear, taste, smell or feel while asleep), waking and sleeping must be affections of one single unifying sense-faculty and controlling sense-organ.14

      In these early reflections on the human faculties, on the conceptual structure necessary to describe them and their exercise, and in these arguments on the need for a sensus communis, we can see the beginnings of systematic scientific thought on the integrative action of the nervous system.

      Two further points before we leave Aristotle:

      The conception of pneuma

      First, like Empedocles, Aristotle believed that there were four sublunary elements: earth, water, air and fire. To this list he added a further supralunary element, ‘the first element’ or ‘the first body’, subsequently called ‘the aether’, from which heavenly bodies are constituted. The sublunary elements naturally move rectilinearly (upwards or downwards). The motion of the first element, or aether, differs: it is (a) eternal, and (b) circular. There is some suggestion that Aristotle may have given some sublunary role to the first element in his biology. In De Generatione Animalium, he wrote:

      Now it is true that the faculty of all kinds of soul seems to have a connection with a matter different from and more divine than the so-called elements … All have in their semen that which causes it to be productive; I mean what is called vital heat. This is not fire nor any such force, but it is the breath (pneuma ) included in the semen and the foam-like, and the natural principle in the breath, being analogous to the element of the stars. (736b29–737a1)

      It is difficult to know what to make of this (let alone how it is meant to be applied to the soul of plants). Cicero, writing some centuries later on the basis of lost works of Aristotle, claimed that

Скачать книгу