Скачать книгу

money for housing and food after having worked their hands to the bone for an entire month. Max Barry masterfully comments on the process, offering the following analysis in his dystopian satire Jennifer Government (2003):

      John Nike was reading a novel called The Space Merchants; it had been reissued and he’d seen a review in Fast Company. They called it ‘prescient and hilarious,’ which John was having a hard time agreeing with. All these old science-fiction books were the same: they thought the future would be dominated by some hard-ass, oppressive Government. Maybe that was plausible back in the 1950s, when the world looked as if it might turn Commie. It sure wasn’t now. (123)

      Dedicating a little more than 300 pages to the depiction of free market capitalism running amok, and introducing characters whose last name and therefore part of their identity is constituted by global economic players (“John Nike”), Barry’s novel belongs to a growing number of books that react to capitalism. Self-reflexively, the passage comments on genre conventions as established by traditional dystopian fictions (the reference to Pohl and Kornbluth’s The Space Merchants is spelled out explicitly), which warn of authoritarian state power. The novel itself, though, shows that the 21st century is by no means comparable to the future envisaged by the classics, but that it differs significantly with regards to the target of criticism: global neoliberal capitalism.

      Despite their acknowledgment of capitalism as a growing problem, these novels and films are rather conservative in nature; they are content with a simple substitution process, adhering to the structures of classical dystopian fiction by simply replacing a totalitarian politician with a totalitarian CEO. This manoeuvre, however, can be no more than a “partial diagnosis” (Sandel 7). As the philosopher Slavoj Žižek has pointed out, these anti-capitalist critiques too often narrow down systemic criticism to individual sins like greed and corruption. John Nike, for instance, is cast in the role of the antagonist for he is willing to advertise the new Nike sneakers by increasing their ‘street credibility,’ having contract killers take aim at Nike’s own customers, creating the illusion that less wealthy individuals might resort to murder to get hold of these shoes. The systemic problems of free market capitalism are reduced to the failed morality of individuals, creating the impression that capitalism per se might work, if we only could eradicate individual flaws (cf. Becker, John, and Schirm 35) – a paradox Žižek considers too narrow a frame to attack capitalism, because the criticism often boils down to condemning pathological individuals. These novels thereby create the illusion that systemic problems (totalitarianism) could be overcome by, on the one hand, initiating a one man show rebellion or, on the other hand, by disposing of individuals like John Nike, who take sole responsibility for deficient structures. Instead of attacking the system, methodological individualism1 will always accuse criminal individuals, who “abus[e] the system” (Fisher 69). Relying on the structures offered by methodological individualism, external criticism as employed by these examples limits its scope of critical analysis – a flaw that has already weakened the anti-capitalist argument of many novels. Further examples include, for instance, industrial novels such as Elizabeth Gaskell’s North and South (1855), which solves its systemic problems of unemployment, horrible working conditions, and growing economic inequality by having one factory owner undergo a Damascene conversion, re-discovering his Christian ideals of charity and altruism (cf. Glomb). Žižek and others repudiate this analysis, claiming that “[w]e should move from this simple moralistic anti-capitalism to more fundamental questions such as why people are pushed to act like that” (Žižek in an interview with Medeiros). Criticising the tendency to burden one individual with the faults of systemic problems, as classical dystopian fiction usually does, Žižek advocates a macro-systemic approach concentrating on the system.

      Adding to Žižek’s position is Jane Bennett’s refusal to cleave to a simplistic pattern of cause and effect, attributing blame for macro-systemic problems to individuals. She states that “[i]n a world of distributed agency, a hesitant attitude toward assigning singular blame becomes a presumptive virtue” (38), advocating a turn away from the methodological individualism of the 19th and 20th century towards a network theory of responsibility.2 Dystopias that have replaced one totalitarian leader with another of a different shade do not attack neoliberal capitalism sustainably, but aim at buffing out the most disturbing aspects.

      Capitalism’s persistence has to do with the inability of ‘external criticism’ – arguably the most commonly drawn weapon, not only by the anti-capitalist dystopias mentioned in the last paragraph, but also in everyday discourse – to formulate critique adequately. This mode is subject to two internal problems and thus fails to attack constructs like neoliberal capitalism for yet again two reasons, upon which the following paragraphs will elaborate. Firstly, while the application of external criticism is a fairly simple procedure, its legitimisation proves to be more complex. External criticism is a technique not uncontested in its efficiency: on the one hand, criteria employed as basis for external criticism are random at best and arbitrary at worst. External criticism derives its maxims from axiomatic deliberations about what constitutes the ‘good life’ – however, external criticism works equally well for less humanist and noble endeavours than promoting positive and negative freedom rights. As Tom Boland correctly points out, this kind of “critique operates as a kind of translation of language, capable of rendering anybody else’s account in derogatory terms. […] These accusations can be directed against anything; businesses, unions, parties, social movements, communities, families, intimate relationships” (“Cacophony”). Totalitarianism might just as easily harness the potential of external criticism to distribute its ideology. On the other hand, it remains unclear which of the many ills suffered by contemporary society actually originate from a capitalist system of production (cf. Jaeggi, “Drei Wege” 321). The concept of exploitation is a case in point: is it a capitalist problem, or is it a general one that happens to re-appear under capitalist rules of production (cf. ibid. 334)? An ethical or moral critique of free market capitalism brought forth by external criticism would first need to establish a normative basis before making a case.

      Secondly, external criticism does not necessarily strive for the best option – the criterium exhausts itself in searching for a better version (not the best), thus running into the danger of substituting one dystopian system with a slightly less dystopian system. Many classical dystopian fictions have been trapped in this fallacy, meaning they propagate one system without sufficient critical examination. Christopher Ferns, for instance, has skilfully deconstructed the revolutionary potential inherent in Orwell’s Nineteen Eighty-Four, arguing that it reproduces the very same system it wants to abolish. He shows that the alternative system the novel hopes to install via the figure of Winston Smith is but a pale shadow of the old one, thus reducing the subversive potential considerably.3 Moreover, Ferns writes that “albeit from a different perspective, [classical] dystopian fiction re-enacts the triumph of an essentially masculine dream of order” (129). Ferns thus confirms the suspicion proclaimed by Theodor W. Adorno in his “Message in a Bottle,” published in Mapping Ideologies (1994), namely that

      [t]hose schooled in dialectical theory are reluctant to indulge in positive images of the proper society, of its members, even of those who would accomplish it. Past traces deter them; in retrospect, all social [e]utopias since Plato’s merge in a dismal resemblance to what they were devised against. The leap into the future, clean over the conditions of the present, lands in the past. (42f.)

      Commenting on the seeming impossibility of ideology-free critique, Tom Boland is correct in his assertion that “the very thing that is ‘unmasked’ is the tool of ‘unmasking’ itself” (Spectacle 2). Any attempt to externally criticise a given society in order to propel an alternative is ultimately doomed to repeat the same mistakes over and over again. “Past traces” will always link the two concepts and thus deter the possibility for radical social change. Nineteen Eighty-Four, its dystopian relatives, and its application of external criticism can thus not be considered subversive or rebellious, changing society for the better. On the contrary, classical dystopian writing is “formally and historically, structurally and contextually, a conservative genre” (Pfaelzer 61).4 Or in the words of Fredric Jameson: “our wildest imaginings are all collages of experience, constructs made up of bits and pieces of the here and now [.] […]

Скачать книгу