Скачать книгу

in mass culture, in which everyday images and objects presented themselves as truly fulfilling, the camp sensibility found in the world an image of failure. In her “Notes on Camp,” published in 1964, Sontag wrote that camp was “the love of the exaggerated, the ‘off,’ of things being-what-they-are-not. . . . Camp sees everything in quotation marks. . . . To perceive Camp in objects and persons is to understand Being-as-Playing-a-Role.”36 Unfortunately for Sontag, the “Camp sensibility” proved exceedingly difficult to pin down for this very reason. Following a few introductory remarks on the necessity of understanding camp as a sensibility, she literally reversed her position. “Not only is there a Camp vision, a Camp way of looking at things,” she wrote, “Camp is as well a quality discoverable in objects and the behavior of persons. . . . It’s not all in the eye of the beholder.”37 To access the “Camp sensibility,” it seems, Sontag felt it necessary to work backward from “campy” objects—things such as Tiffany lamps, the National Enquirer, Flash Gordon comics, and the famous Brown Derby restaurant in Los Angeles. By looking to “the canon of Camp,” she believed it would be possible to extrapolate those characteristics that appealed to—and conditioned—“the Camp eye.”38 Through a brief survey of these objects, she surmised that camp could not be overly serious, overly important, or overly good: “Many examples of Camp are things which, from a ‘serious’ point of view, are either bad art or kitsch.”39 The camp object was one that proclaimed, whether naively or consciously, its own silliness, extravagance, or artificiality. It was an object in which form and content failed to coalesce. Like Baudelaire’s concept of the “significative comic,” the camp object was “visibly double.”40

      But it was the relation of camp’s practitioners—as opposed to its objects—to another of Baudelaire’s concepts that Sontag found more worrisome. As she understood it, camp amounted to the reformulation of dandyism for the world of mass culture. Its intimate ties to mass culture, however, had effectively expunged the dandy’s “quintessence of character and . . . subtle understanding of the entire moral mechanism of this world.”41 In place of this character and understanding was mere “aestheticism.” Camp’s affected pleasure in the imperfections of the everyday was thus nothing more than the latest moment in the “history of snob taste.”42 More importantly, though, camp had only taken hold at a moment when “no authentic aristocrats in the old sense exist . . . to sponsor special tastes.”43 In the absence of a true upper class “an improvised self-elected class, mainly homosexuals,” had come to serve as the “aristocrats of taste.”44 Camp’s appreciation of the mundane, its celebration of the art of the masses, could never have been mistaken for a truly populist—or even avant-garde—project. Rather, it was precisely the opposite.45 Unlike “true” artists, those who appreciated camp were virtually incapable of developing any deeper understanding of the world. Rather than providing a challenge to critical thought, they had merely inverted its standards.

Скачать книгу