ТОП просматриваемых книг сайта:
The Perspective of Love. R. J. Snell
Читать онлайн.Название The Perspective of Love
Год выпуска 0
isbn 9781630873431
Автор произведения R. J. Snell
Жанр Религия: прочее
Издательство Ingram
I’ll save the question of the innateness of natural law for later, although clearly I doubt innateness as pictured by common sense. But this pattern of “in” and “out” pervades common sense 3, with natural law thought to reside in things, but by this they mean nature as the physical world. Natural law is modeled after the properties innate in physical reality, and natural law is the ordo naturae.
Law in Nature, Enchanted or Disenchanted
In one form, the ordo naturae is a kind of cosmic-mysticism where the divine ordering principle of the universe operates within nature to render it cosmos rather than chaos, with an isomorphism between the ordering principle of the macrocosm and the microcosm of soul or city. To live according to nature is to follow the principle of order (arche, logos, physei dikaion, theios nomos). In each formulation, the ordering principle is symbolized as governing the entire cosmos, with a unity or parallel between the laws of nature, the laws of the city, and the laws of the soul—metaphysics, physics, politics, and ethics are, in a real if confused sense, about the same thing.75
Following Eliade, Merold Westphal identifies in mimetic forms of religion such commitment to nature, “not simply or primarily because nature is the primary manifestation of the divine, but because through worship human existence is to be assimilated to the natural order,” insofar as worship comports and imitates itself to the rhythms and forces operative in nature.76 Through ritual imitation, religion “seeks to integrate human existence into the natural cosmos,” in such a way that the distinction between ritual and mundane life is rather porous, but the order “in” nature becomes incorporated “into” one’s own life through mimesis.
In philosophical rather than religious history, the natural philosophy of the pre-Socratics, “started by inquiring into the origin of the universe, its physis,” was as much a metaphysical study as empirical, for the natural principles were thought to underlie and order “the comprehension of everything which proceeds from that order and now exists.”77 While each thinker and school presented their own account, the tendency was towards a greater connection between the laws governing the cosmos and all other aspects “in ‘the nature of being’ . . . in the spiritual world,” so as to find order and method in human life.”78 The turn from natural philosophy to the human things, as Socrates recounted his own biography, was already underway: “The experience of being activates man to the reality of order in himself and in the cosmos . . . the experience of being is the primary experience of the cosmos in which man is consubstantial with the things of his environment, a partnership that in philosophy is heightened to the awake consciousness of the community of order uniting thought and being.”79
In its pre-Socratic beginnings, philosophy, like earlier mythic or theological speculations, “attempts to find the origin of the cosmos in elementary forces,” although “the gods of polytheism are excluded from it,” leading to “the dissociation of a cosmos-full-of-gods into a dedivinized order of things.”80 Being, rather than the gods, is the unknown arche, the heuristic x, and thus metaphysics becomes the discourse concerning nature. Still, being is articulated as a material principle, whether as water, or air, or fire, or logos, but like mimetic religion the arche “stands at the beginning like a god from whose initiative a chain of events passes right down to the being that is experienced here and now,” the study of which is not merely abstract but intimately connected to the right, or natural, way to live.81 Asking, “what is right by nature?” still turns to forces outside of us, even if somehow coterminous (even innate) with our thought. Natural law is nature itself, or at least the principles of nature which comprise and govern all that is—us too.
Clearly I’m simplifying a complex development in the history of ideas and culture, but I’m trying to present a taxonomy rather than comprehensive history; my point is merely to demonstrate the possibility of a development in natural law which in its mode of inquiry is beholden to common sense in conceiving order as something which could be operative out there, or out there in nature, or as nature, even if mirrored in the “in here” of intellect.82 Nor are attempts to read law in nature relics from a previous time. Martin Rhonheimer, for one, thinks that such “physicalist” accounts dominated both neoscholasticism and revisionism into the current century:
This means that, within the perspective of certain academic trends (in which a large number of contemporary moral theologians have been educated), the natural law is frequently understood as an object of knowledge that lies, somehow, in the nature of things, over against the practical reason. . . . In close connection with this foreshortened conception of the natural law can be found a derivation of moral norms from a naturally (“physicalistically”) understood reality. . . . This is a result of identifying the lex naturalis—in the sense of modern scientific law—with a natural order that lies in the being of things; it means understanding the concept of a “natural order” (ordo naturalis) that lies beneath the “ought” in such a way that the reason is reduced to an organ that merely “reads off” what “is” and prescribes what “ought” to be.83
For someone like Rhonheimer, however, lex naturalis does not mean what it is often taken to mean, as “some external standard ‘out there’” or “in the heart,” as we’ll see.84
Concluding Thoughts
I opened this chapter referring to J. Budziszewski’s explanation that all versions of natural law, whatever their differences, hold that law is somehow “embedded into the structure of creation, especially human nature. . . .” No doubt this is true, but much depends on the little word “into.” The history of natural law, including current proponents, includes common sense readings of “into,” and, in fact, includes several different types of common sense readings: (1) natural law as found in inclinations, (2) natural law as found in the intuitive meanings of intersubjective community, and (3) natural law as in nature. Each expression operates within the common sense mode of meaning which (1) begins with and is largely limited to non-theoretical, albeit still intelligent, descriptions of very powerful experiences, (2) codified and shared within community and its educational forms, often through proverbs and authority articulating successful ways of living and acting, and (3) viewing the real in a common sense grasp of the bodies, or the “already out there now real,” known through a kind of objectivity which grasps ordering principles of the real. For each type of common sense natural law, “nature” corresponds to a certain pattern of interest or care, emerging as the heuristic in keeping with that same pattern of care. Nature, for common sense, is the ordering pattern of that which is most real to us, as experienced by us, whether in our passions, or our community, or our religion, and even in our attempts to articulate the grounds of being. Law, for such meaning, is the order found in nature, an order which we do not create or constitute but rather find always already operative, not of our own devising; law is the order of nature, the ordo naturae.
Already, though, certain tensions and patterns emerge prompting the transition to a new differentiation of