Скачать книгу

Parisian dominican Peter of Tarantasia (who was elected Pope Innocent V shortly before his death in 1276)98 asked questions of a form familiar to us from our discussion of the sacrament of the altar: can baptism be conferred by evil ministers?99 and, may a better baptism be had from a better minister?100 In part adapting materials which Aquinas had used in his more general quaestio, “can the sacraments be conferred by evil ministers?”101 Peter puts forward these opinions: a bad man is not a fit minister of the sacrament of baptism, a dead member does not serve others as an effective channel, and no-one can serve two masters (cf. Matthew 6:24), the devil and Christ together. Hence an evil minister cannot confer baptism. On the other hand, Peter continues, Augustine says that baptism may be given by a man who is a drunkard, a murderer, given to whatever evil (this actually follows Peter Lombard’s review of the problem). And it is held that in extremis baptism can be conferred by a Jew, a pagan, or a heretic: therefore it can be conferred by any type of sinner.

      Peter’s responsio explains that certain things pertain to the substance of the sacrament while others pertain to propriety, i.e., the behavior which is appropriate for its conferral. If substantial things are lacking, the sacrament is not valid; if things relating to propriety are lacking, the sacrament is unaffected. Furthermore, in time of necessity probity is relatively unimportant, and as far as the “dead member” is concerned, the influx involved is not internal (relating to the person’s own spiritual situation) but external, as coming from God. Besides, in certain actions to be a servant of the devil is to serve God, or to be his minister. But does an evil minister really confer an effective sacrament? Ecclesiasticus 34:4 rightly asks, “who can be made clean by the unclean?” An evil minister is not an effective mediator; and nothing can give what it hasn’t got itself. Against all this, however, is the argument that water may be conducted to the plains by a stone channel;102 similarly, grace may be conveyed by a bad minister to the recipients of the sacrament. Furthermore, an individual’s salvation should not be dependent on the life of someone else. And a doctor who has a corporeal infirmity is nevertheless able to cure someone else corporeally; the same is true of the spiritual doctor, who effects spiritual healing.

      Can a better baptism be had from a better minister? After all, the better the agent the better the action. A multiplicity of causes results in a multiplicity of effects; when a holy man baptizes, the cause of grace is multiplied and therefore the effect is multiplied, and should not one desire as many good effects as possible? Furthermore, whoever is more enlightened is better able to enlighten others, and the more learned person is better able to teach others. However, as Augustine says, a better person does not give better baptism. This actually follows Peter Lombard’s own statement, “Nec melior est baptismus qui per meliorem datur,” which the Lombard had backed up with a summary of part of Augustine’s fifth tractate on the Gospel of John.103 Furthermore, Peter of Tarantasia continues, a good minister does not dispense better alms than a bad one. And, if the evil of a bad minister doesn’t diminish the effect of his baptism, therefore the goodness of a good one doesn’t augment the goodness of his. Peter’s utterly predictable answer is that in substantial matters the operation of a good minister isn’t of greater value than a good one, because God here operates as auctor, and the man as mere minister.

      Peter then moves on to ask if baptism can be given by those who do not have holy orders, whether lay people or angels.104 His responsio brings out the fact that baptism is the sacrament of maximum necessity, because neither children nor adults may be saved without it. In extremis any kind of water suffices for baptism, and any man can give it. Indeed, Peter had said a little earlier that in the case of necessity even an old woman (vetula) can perform an efficacious baptism.105 That view was commonplace. Albert the Great, for instance, had affirmed that “When an old woman baptizes, the baptism actually does take place” (vetula baptizat, et baptizatum est), emphasizing that in casu necessitatis the person performing this rite does not have to be of the masculine sex, have holy orders or jurisdiction, or be living a good life.106 However, no-one actually recommended this course of action, or thought for a moment that it should be the norm. Ideally, an ordained minister should do the deed, just as proper holy water should be used, as Peter of Tarantasia (typically) emphasizes. He sums up by saying that the bestowal of baptism may be justified on two grounds: either with reference to authoritative office, which applies solely to a priest, or ex iuris permissione (i.e., in accordance with what is legally permitted), which applies to others, chiefly in case of necessity. But what about angels? They cannot baptize or consecrate ex officio, Peter explains, but only by special divine mandate. And, the angel in question must be a good one— in this very special case, it would seem, individual goodness does matter after all.

      As far as lay people are concerned, however, personal virtue or vice is irrelevant in the emergency conferral of baptism. The schoolmen are utterly unanimous on that point, and there is little variation in how the issue is handled.107 However, Thomas Aquinas isolates and treats separately the specific question, can a woman baptize?108 He begins by quoting the Council of Carthage’s prohibition: “A woman, no matter how learned and holy, should not presume to teach men in public assembly or to baptize others.”109 Given that it is perfectly clear that women cannot teach publicly (it being “shameful for a woman to speak in church”; I Corinthians 14:35), it would seem that they cannot baptize either. Moreover, baptism belongs to the prelatical office (the officium praelationis), and thus should be dispensed by priests who have the cure of souls. Because women cannot hold this office (“I permit no woman to teach or to have authority over men”; I Timothy 2:12), they lack the authority to baptize. Aquinas then embarks on a somewhat bizarre excursus. In the spiritual rebirth of baptism “water seems to take the place of the maternal womb.” But the person who baptizes “seems rather to have the task of father (patris officium)”: this is not fitting for a woman, and therefore a woman cannot baptize. This assertion is set up only to be knocked down, of course, but its deficiency as an argument is particularly glaring: a woman’s material possession of a womb means that a body-metaphor relating to spiritual matters works against her, destroying her case to be allowed to baptize.

      Not one of Aquinas’s better moments. Still, he does invoke the contrast between the material and the spiritual in his response. In human generation, male and female function in accordance with their different natures, the male being active and the female passive. “So a woman cannot be the active principle of generation but the passive only.” But in spiritual generation people work not by their own powers but as instruments of the power of Christ, and therefore both men and women can baptize in casu necessitatis. One might interrogate this position further, and ask, if in certain spiritual matters men and women operate not in accordance with their different and distinctive natures but as the equal instruments of a higher agency, is there not a basis here for treating male and female equally in respect of their right to preach and indeed to confect the Eucharist?

      But of course Aquinas does not go down that route; for that sort of argument we will have to await the Lollard theology of Walter Brut and John Purvey (as discussed in Chapter 3 below). What Aquinas does say here is that a woman, although not permitted to teach publicly (publice docere), can nevertheless “instruct and admonish privately” (potest tamen privata doctrina vel monitione aliquem instruere): on the same argument, while she may not baptize publicly and solemnly she can baptize “in case of necessity.” For the purposes of this argument, then, baptism in necessitate is put on a par with private teaching. And the emphasis is very much on what is permissible in the most extreme of circumstances. If there is a capable layman present, then he should perform the baptism rather than a woman; if there is a cleric present the layman should defer to him; and of course if an ordained priest is available, he must do the job. Aquinas cites I Corinthians 11:3 in justification: “the head of a woman is man and the head of man is Christ.” So, if and only if there is no supposedly superior individual available, should a woman act. The rigidity of this hierarchical system somewhat undermines the apparent inclusiveness of the auctoritates with which Aquinas had started his responsio. There it had been affirmed that Christ principally baptizes, so the person of whatever sex “on whom you see the spirit descend and remain” (John 1:33) can perform the physical action, particularly in view of the fact that “in Christ

Скачать книгу