Скачать книгу

are accompanied by heavily mathematized (therefore consistent) models. For instance, the fact that some statement is a true knowledge in mathematical sciences does not imply it is true in economics. Always remember: a mathematically consistent model is not synonymous with a scientific theory.

      Philosophy, like science, is also a theoretical discourse but with a very important difference: it works by demarcating positions as correct or incorrect based on its own philosophical system that defines categories and their relations [8]. Unlike scientific proofs, philosophy works through rational argumentation to defend positions (i.e. theses), usually trying to answer universal and timeless questions about, for example, existence of freedom. In this case, philosophy has no specific (concrete) object as sciences do; consequently, it is not a science in the way we just defined. Philosophy then becomes its own practice: rational argumentation based on a totalizing system of categories defining positions about everything that exists or not. Following this line of thought, philosophy is not a science of sciences; it can neither judge the truth value of propositions internally established by the different sciences nor state de jure conditions for scientific knowledge from the outside.

      Besides, scientific and philosophical practices exist among several other social practices. They are part of an articulated historical social whole, where different practices coexist and interfere with each other at certain degrees and levels of effectivity. As previously discussed, scientific practice produces general objective true knowledge about abstract objects, which very usually contradicts the commonsense ideas that are usually related to immediate representations arising from other social practices of our daily lives. This clearly leads to obstacles to scientists, who are both agents of the scientific practice and individuals living in society. The totalizing tendency of philosophy also plays a role: it either distorts scientific theories and concepts to fit in universal systems of philosophical categories or judges their truth value based on universal methodological assumptions. This directly or indirectly affects the self‐understanding of the relation that the scientists have with their own practice, creating new obstacles to the science development [9, 10].

      In addition to this unavoidable challenge, the rationalization required by scientific theories appears in different forms. In this case, philosophical practice can help scientific practice by classifying the different types of rationality depending on the object under consideration. Motivated by Lepskiy [11] (but understood here in a different manner) and Althusser [8], we propose the following division.

       Classical scientific rationality: Direct observations and empirical falsification are possible for all elements of the theory, i.e. there is a one‐to‐one map between the physical and abstract realities.

       Nonclassical scientific rationality: Observations are not directly possible, i.e. the process of abstraction leads to nonobservable steps, resulting in a relatively autonomous theoretical domain.

       Interventionist scientific rationality: Active elements with internal awareness with objectives and goals exist, leading to a theory of the fact to be accomplished in contrast to theories of the accomplished facts.

      By acknowledging the differences between these forms of rationality, sciences and scientific knowledge can be internalized as a social practice within the existing mode of production. Different from positivist and existentialist traditions in philosophy, this practice of philosophy attempts to articulate the scientific practice within the historical social whole, critically building demarcations of the correctness of the reach of scientific knowledge by rational argumentation [10].

      This philosophical practice goes hand in hand with the scientific practice by helping scientists to avoid overreaching tendencies related to their own theoretical findings. It also indicates critical points where other practices might be interfering in the scientific activity and vice versa. Although a deep discussion of the complex relations between scientific practice and other practices are far beyond our aim here, we will throughout this book deal with one specific relation: how scientific practice is related to the technological development. We have seen so far that the practical development of techniques does not require the intervention of (abstract) scientific rationalization. On the other hand, the knowledge produced by the sciences has a lot to offer to practical techniques. The existence of the term technology, referring to techniques developed or rectified by the sciences, indicates such a relation. More than what this definition might suggest, technology cannot be simply reduced to a mere application of scientific knowledge; it can indeed create new domains and objects subject to a new scientific discourse.

      The aforementioned control and information theories perfectly exemplify this. New technological artifacts had been constructed using the up‐to‐date knowledge of physical laws to solve specific concrete problems, almost in a trial‐and‐error basis to create know‐how‐type of knowledge pushed by the needs of the industrial revolution. At some point, these concrete artifacts were conceptualized as abstract objects toward a scientific theory with its own methods, proofs, and research questions, constituting a relatively autonomous science of specific technological objects. The new established science not only indicates how to improve the efficiency of existing techniques and/or artifacts but also (and very importantly) defines their fundamental characteristics, conditions, and limits.

Скачать книгу