Скачать книгу

induce the body to produce endorphins. Many forms of enhancement may serve medical goals. Once again, the therapy–enhancement distinction appears not to set any firm moral boundaries in genetic medicine.

      One might attempt to avoid this problem by narrowly construing the goals of medicine: the goals of medicine are to treat and prevent diseases in human beings. Other uses of medical technology do not serve the goals of medicine. There are two problems with this response. First, it assumes that we agree on the goals of medicine and the definitions of health and disease. Second, even if we could agree that medicine’s goals are to treat and prevent diseases and we can define “health” and “disease,” why would it be immoral to use medical technology and science for nonmedical purposes? If a medical procedure, such as mastectomy, is developed for therapeutic purposes, what is wrong with using that procedure for “nonmedical” purposes, such as breast reduction surgery in men with overdeveloped breasts? Admittedly, there are many morally troubling nonmedical uses of medical science and technology, such as the use of steroids by athletes and the use of laxatives by anorexics, but these morally troubling uses of medicine are morally troubling because they violate various moral principles or values, such as fairness and nonmaleficence, not because they are nonmedical uses of medicine.

      One might argue that those who use medical science and technology for nonmedical purposes violate medicine’s professional norms, but this point only applies to those who consider themselves to be medical professionals. If a procedure violates medical norms, it is medically unethical, but this does not mean that the procedure is unethical outside of the context of medical care. For example, the American Medical Association holds that it is unethical for physicians to assist the state in executions, but this policy does not constitute an unconditional argument against capital punishment. To make the case against capital punishment, one must appeal to wider moral and political norms. Hence the goals of medicine also do not set a morally sharp dividing line between genetic therapy and enhancement.

      1 physical traits and abilities, such as an opposable thumb, bipedalism, etc.

      2 psychosocial traits and abilities, such as cognition, language, emotional responses, sociality, etc.

      3 phylogenetic traits, such as membership in the biological species Homo sapiens.

      The beings that we call “human” possess many of these traits and abilities, even though some humans have more of these traits and abilities than others. For example, a newborn and an adult have many of the same physical and phylogenetic traits and abilities, even though the adult has more psychosocial traits and abilities. For my purposes, I do not need to say which of these traits and abilities are more “central” to the concept of humanness, since I am not defending a definition that provides necessary or sufficient conditions.

Скачать книгу