Скачать книгу

that redistricting should be thought of as a periodic adjustment to the foundational rules of the political system. The former will necessarily be ‘political’ and partisan; the latter aims to be apolitical and non-partisan.

      The realpolitik redistricting argument rests on the assumption that no process involving political actors can be apolitical, nor can the product of such a process be neutral. Even if some such processes could be apolitical, redistricting is not likely to be one of them. As the political scientist Justin Buchler explains, given the winner-take-all nature of legislative districts in the United States, the procedures for drawing district boundaries will inevitably determine winners and losers, broadly defined, in those districts. Indeed, according to Buchler, choices about redistricting rules are “indistinguishable from the question of who should win and who should lose.”22 This holds both for the choice of actors responsible for redistricting and for the specific decision-making rules those actors choose to utilize to draw maps. “Thus,” writes Buchler, “there can be no apolitical redistricting in any meaningful sense of the term because the choice of delegation is as ‘political’ as the choice of algorithm.”23

      Critical to the realpolitik argument is the claim that voters aren’t powerless in the process. They know that redistricting takes place in the year following the census and they can vote for candidates who will draw lines the way they’d prefer them to be drawn. As the political commentator Kevin Williamson puts it,

      If Democrats are unhappy with Republican domination of the state legislatures and governorships – and they should be unhappy – then they have a much more direct option [than going to court]: They can go into the states and ask people for their votes in legislative races and in gubernatorial elections. If they find that route difficult, then maybe the Democrats should be rethinking what they’re trying to sell people.26

      According to this view, when the voters put one party in charge of the entire post-census legislative process, they are likely to be satisfied with the legislative maps that party draws. (If, on the other hand, voters produce divided government – that is, control of at least one chamber in the state legislature is in the hands of one party while the governor is a member of the other party – then they apparently prefer compromise in the redistricting process.)

      Finally, this perspective maintains that the rules of the game were established at the founding of the country, when the Constitution was adopted. Those rules – essentially, the Constitution – can be amended, but that process itself is provided for in the Constitution. However, in the absence of an attempt to change the Constitution, formally or informally as part of what might be referred to as “constitutional politics,” “normal politics” reigns.28 Normal politics is the familiar, day-to-day struggle over “who gets what, when, and how,” as the political scientist Harold Lasswell famously put it.29 Redistricting, then, is simply part of normal politics.

      One might argue, of course, that the Constitution forbids partisan gerrymandering. We will consider that argument in a later chapter. For now, suffice it to say that the realpolitik viewpoint does not believe partisan gerrymandering is constitutionally prohibited. To understand why, it’s worth quoting law professors Larry Alexander and Saikrishna Prakash at length:

      The countervailing viewpoint, the civic redistricting perspective, acknowledges that neutrality in human processes is difficult to achieve. Nonetheless, it takes the position that we should strive to find a set of rules governing the operation of elections that both parties (or, indeed, all parties) can accept. Without opening a Pandora’s box of contemporary political theory, this position is grounded in the notion of public reason and the claim that political actors ought to be reasonable in their public deliberations.31 To be reasonable, a person must be willing “to live by rules that can be justified to similarly motivated citizens on grounds that they could accept.”32 There is, then, an important element of reciprocity at work here. What is fair for one side ought to be fair for the other (or others). We’ll find a version of reciprocity later in the book in the concept of partisan symmetry.

      is to view appropriate democratic politics as akin in important respects to a robustly competitive market – a market whose vitality depends on both clear rules of engagement and on the ritual cleansing born of competition. Only through an appropriately competitive partisan environment can one of the central goals of democratic politics be realized: that the policy outcomes of the political process be responsive to the interests and views of citizens. But politics shares with all markets a vulnerability to anticompetitive behavior.

Скачать книгу